-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
Copy pathLogic.v
1996 lines (1611 loc) · 64.7 KB
/
Logic.v
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
(** * Logic: Logic in Coq *)
Set Warnings "-notation-overridden,-parsing".
Set Warnings "-deprecated-hint-without-locality".
Require Nat.
From LF Require Export Tactics.
(** We have now seen many examples of factual claims (_propositions_)
and ways of presenting evidence of their truth (_proofs_). In
particular, we have worked extensively with equality
propositions ([e1 = e2]), implications ([P -> Q]), and quantified
propositions ([forall x, P]). In this chapter, we will see how
Coq can be used to carry out other familiar forms of logical
reasoning.
Before diving into details, we should talk a bit about the status of
mathematical statements in Coq. Recall that Coq is a _typed_
language, which means that every sensible expression has an
associated type. Logical claims are no exception: any statement
we might try to prove in Coq has a type, namely [Prop], the type
of _propositions_. We can see this with the [Check] command: *)
Check (forall n m : nat, n + m = m + n) : Prop.
(** Note that _all_ syntactically well-formed propositions have type
[Prop] in Coq, regardless of whether they are true.
Simply _being_ a proposition is one thing; being _provable_ is
a different thing! *)
Check 2 = 2 : Prop.
Check 3 = 2 : Prop.
Check forall n : nat, n = 2 : Prop.
(** Indeed, propositions don't just have types -- they are
_first-class_ entities that can be manipulated in all the same ways as
any of the other things in Coq's world. *)
(** So far, we've seen one primary place that propositions can appear:
in [Theorem] (and [Lemma] and [Example]) declarations. *)
Theorem plus_2_2_is_4 :
2 + 2 = 4.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
(** But propositions can be used in other ways. For example, we
can give a name to a proposition using a [Definition], just as we
give names to other kinds of expressions. *)
Definition plus_claim : Prop := 2 + 2 = 4.
Check plus_claim : Prop.
(** We can later use this name in any situation where a proposition is
expected -- for example, as the claim in a [Theorem] declaration. *)
Theorem plus_claim_is_true :
plus_claim.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
(** We can also write _parameterized_ propositions -- that is,
functions that take arguments of some type and return a
proposition. *)
(** For instance, the following function takes a number
and returns a proposition asserting that this number is equal to
three: *)
Definition is_three (n : nat) : Prop :=
n = 3.
Check is_three : nat -> Prop.
(** In Coq, functions that return propositions are said to define
_properties_ of their arguments.
For instance, here's a (polymorphic) property defining the
familiar notion of an _injective function_. *)
Definition injective {A B} (f : A -> B) :=
forall x y : A, f x = f y -> x = y.
Lemma succ_inj : injective S.
Proof.
intros n m H. injection H as H1. apply H1.
Qed.
(** The familiar equality operator [=] is a (binary) function that returns
a [Prop].
The expression [n = m] is syntactic sugar for [eq n m] (defined in
Coq's standard library using the [Notation] mechanism).
Because [eq] can be used with elements of any type, it is also
polymorphic: *)
Check @eq : forall A : Type, A -> A -> Prop.
(** (Notice that we wrote [@eq] instead of [eq]: The type
argument [A] to [eq] is declared as implicit, and we need to turn
off the inference of this implicit argument to see the full type
of [eq].) *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Logical Connectives *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Conjunction *)
(** The _conjunction_, or _logical and_, of propositions [A] and [B] is
written [A /\ B]; it represents the claim that both [A] and [B] are
true. *)
Example and_example : 3 + 4 = 7 /\ 2 * 2 = 4.
(** To prove a conjunction, use the [split] tactic. This will generate
two subgoals, one for each part of the statement: *)
Proof.
split.
- (* 3 + 4 = 7 *) reflexivity.
- (* 2 * 2 = 4 *) reflexivity.
Qed.
(** For any propositions [A] and [B], if we assume that [A] is true and
that [B] is true, we can conclude that [A /\ B] is also true. The Coq
library provides a function [conj] that does this. *)
Check @conj : forall A B : Prop, A -> B -> A /\ B.
(** Since applying a theorem with hypotheses to some goal has the effect of
generating as many subgoals as there are hypotheses for that theorem,
we can apply [conj] to achieve the same effect as [split]. *)
Example and_example' : 3 + 4 = 7 /\ 2 * 2 = 4.
Proof.
apply conj.
- (* 3 + 4 = 7 *) reflexivity.
- (* 2 + 2 = 4 *) reflexivity.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard (and_exercise) *)
Lemma zero_uniq:
forall n m : nat, n + m = 0 -> n = 0.
Proof.
intros n m H0.
destruct n eqn:N.
- destruct m eqn:M.
+ reflexivity.
+ reflexivity.
- discriminate.
Qed.
Example and_exercise :
forall n m : nat, n + m = 0 -> n = 0 /\ m = 0.
Search eqb.
Proof.
intros n m H.
apply conj.
generalize dependent H.
- apply zero_uniq.
- pose proof H as H0. apply zero_uniq in H0. rewrite -> H0 in H. simpl in H. apply H.
Qed.
(** [] *)
(** So much for proving conjunctive statements. To go in the other
direction -- i.e., to _use_ a conjunctive hypothesis to help prove
something else -- we employ the [destruct] tactic.
When the current proof context contains a hypothesis [H] of the
form [A /\ B], writing [destruct H as [HA HB]] will remove [H]
from the context and replace it with two new hypotheses: [HA],
stating that [A] is true, and [HB], stating that [B] is true. *)
Lemma and_example2 :
forall n m : nat, n = 0 /\ m = 0 -> n + m = 0.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros n m H.
destruct H as [Hn Hm].
rewrite Hn. rewrite Hm.
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** As usual, we can also destruct [H] right when we introduce it,
instead of introducing and then destructing it: *)
Lemma and_example2' :
forall n m : nat, n = 0 /\ m = 0 -> n + m = 0.
Proof.
intros n m [Hn Hm].
rewrite Hn. rewrite Hm.
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** You may wonder why we bothered packing the two hypotheses [n = 0] and
[m = 0] into a single conjunction, since we could also have stated the
theorem with two separate premises: *)
Lemma and_example2'' :
forall n m : nat, n = 0 -> m = 0 -> n + m = 0.
Proof.
intros n m Hn Hm.
rewrite Hn. rewrite Hm.
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** For this specific theorem, both formulations are fine. But it's
important to understand how to work with conjunctive hypotheses because
conjunctions often arise from intermediate steps in proofs, especially
in larger developments.
Here's a simple example: *)
Lemma and_example3 :
forall n m : nat, n + m = 0 -> n * m = 0.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros n m H.
apply and_exercise in H.
destruct H as [Hn Hm].
rewrite Hn. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** Another common situation is that we know [A /\ B] but in some context
we need just [A] or just [B]. In such cases we can do a
[destruct] (possibly as part of an [intros]) and use an underscore
pattern [_] to indicate that the unneeded conjunct should just be
thrown away. *)
Lemma proj1 : forall P Q : Prop,
P /\ Q -> P.
Proof.
intros P Q HPQ.
destruct HPQ as [HP _].
apply HP. Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, standard, optional (proj2) *)
Lemma proj2 : forall P Q : Prop,
P /\ Q -> Q.
Proof.
intros P Q H0.
destruct H0 as [H1 H2].
- apply H2.
Qed.
(** [] *)
(** Finally, we sometimes need to rearrange the order of conjunctions
and/or the grouping of multi-way conjunctions. The following
commutativity and associativity theorems can be handy in such
cases. *)
Theorem and_commut : forall P Q : Prop,
P /\ Q -> Q /\ P.
Proof.
intros P Q [HP HQ].
split.
- (* left *) apply HQ.
- (* right *) apply HP. Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard (and_assoc)
(In the following proof of associativity, notice how the _nested_
[intros] pattern breaks the hypothesis [H : P /\ (Q /\ R)] down into
[HP : P], [HQ : Q], and [HR : R]. Finish the proof.) *)
Theorem and_assoc : forall P Q R : Prop,
P /\ (Q /\ R) -> (P /\ Q) /\ R.
Proof.
intros P Q R [HP [HQ HR]].
split.
- split.
+ apply HP.
+ apply HQ.
- apply HR.
Qed.
(** [] *)
(** Finally, the infix notation [/\] is actually just syntactic sugar for
[and A B]. That is, [and] is a Coq operator that takes two
propositions as arguments and yields a proposition. *)
Check and : Prop -> Prop -> Prop.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Disjunction *)
(** Another important connective is the _disjunction_, or _logical or_,
of two propositions: [A \/ B] is true when either [A] or [B]
is. This infix notation stands for [or A B], where [or : Prop ->
Prop -> Prop]. *)
(** To use a disjunctive hypothesis in a proof, we proceed by case
analysis -- which, as with other data types like [nat], can be done
explicitly with [destruct] or implicitly with an [intros]
pattern: *)
Lemma factor_is_O:
forall n m : nat, n = 0 \/ m = 0 -> n * m = 0.
Proof.
(* This pattern implicitly does case analysis on
[n = 0 \/ m = 0] *)
intros n m [Hn | Hm].
- (* Here, [n = 0] *)
rewrite Hn. reflexivity.
- (* Here, [m = 0] *)
rewrite Hm. rewrite <- mult_n_O.
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** Conversely, to show that a disjunction holds, it suffices to show that
one of its sides holds. This can be done via the tactics [left] and
[right]. As their names imply, the first one requires proving the left
side of the disjunction, while the second requires proving the right
side. Here is a trivial use... *)
Lemma or_intro_l : forall A B : Prop, A -> A \/ B.
Proof.
intros A B HA.
left.
apply HA.
Qed.
(** ... and here is a slightly more interesting example requiring both
[left] and [right]: *)
Lemma zero_or_succ :
forall n : nat, n = 0 \/ n = S (pred n).
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros [|n'].
- left. reflexivity.
- right. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, standard (mult_is_O) *)
Lemma mult_is_O :
forall n m, n * m = 0 -> n = 0 \/ m = 0.
Proof.
intros n m.
induction n as [| n' IHn'].
- left. reflexivity.
- destruct m eqn:M.
+ right. reflexivity.
+ right. discriminate.
Qed.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, standard (or_commut) *)
Theorem or_commut : forall P Q : Prop,
P \/ Q -> Q \/ P.
Proof.
intros P Q [HP | HQ].
- right. apply HP.
- left. apply HQ.
Qed.
(** [] *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Falsehood and Negation
Up to this point, we have mostly been concerned with proving "positive"
statements -- addition is commutative, appending lists is associative,
etc. Of course, we are sometimes also interested in negative results,
demonstrating that some given proposition is _not_ true. Such
statements are expressed with the logical negation operator [~]. *)
(** To see how negation works, recall the _principle of explosion_
from the [Tactics] chapter, which asserts that, if we assume a
contradiction, then any other proposition can be derived.
Following this intuition, we could define [~ P] ("not [P]") as
[forall Q, P -> Q].
Coq actually makes a slightly different but equivalent choice,
defining [~ P] as [P -> False], where [False] is a specific
un-provable proposition defined in the standard library. *)
Module NotPlayground.
Definition not (P:Prop) := P -> False.
Check not : Prop -> Prop.
Notation "~ x" := (not x) : type_scope.
End NotPlayground.
(** Since [False] is a contradictory proposition, the principle of
explosion also applies to it. If we can get [False] into the context,
we can use [destruct] on it to complete any goal: *)
Theorem ex_falso_quodlibet : forall (P:Prop),
False -> P.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros P contra.
destruct contra. Qed.
(** The Latin _ex falso quodlibet_ means, literally, "from falsehood
follows whatever you like"; this is another common name for the
principle of explosion. *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (not_implies_our_not)
Show that Coq's definition of negation implies the intuitive one
mentioned above.
Hint: while getting accustomed to Coq's definition of [not], you might
find it helpful to [unfold not] near the beginning of proofs. *)
Theorem not_implies_our_not : forall (P:Prop),
~ P -> (forall (Q:Prop), P -> Q).
Proof.
unfold not.
intros P HP Q P'.
apply HP in P'. destruct P'.
Qed.
(** [] *)
(** Inequality is a very common form of negated statement, so there is a
special notation for it:
Notation "x <> y" := (~(x = y)).
*)
(** For example: *)
Theorem zero_not_one : 0 <> 1.
Proof.
(** The proposition [0 <> 1] is exactly the same as
[~(0 = 1)] -- that is, [not (0 = 1)] -- which unfolds to
[(0 = 1) -> False]. (We use [unfold not] explicitly here,
to illustrate that point, but generally it can be omitted.) *)
unfold not.
(** To prove an inequality, we may assume the opposite
equality... *)
intros contra.
(** ... and deduce a contradiction from it. Here, the
equality [O = S O] contradicts the disjointness of
constructors [O] and [S], so [discriminate] takes care
of it. *)
discriminate contra.
Qed.
(** It takes a little practice to get used to working with negation in Coq.
Even though _you_ can see perfectly well why a statement involving
negation is true, it can be a little tricky at first to see how to make
Coq understand it!
Here are proofs of a few familiar facts to help get you warmed up. *)
Theorem not_False :
~ False.
Proof.
unfold not. intros H. destruct H. Qed.
Theorem contradiction_implies_anything : forall P Q : Prop,
(P /\ ~P) -> Q.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros P Q [HP HNA]. unfold not in HNA.
apply HNA in HP. destruct HP. Qed.
Theorem double_neg : forall P : Prop,
P -> ~~P.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros P H. unfold not. intros G. apply G. apply H. Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, advanced (double_neg_inf)
Write an _informal_ proof of [double_neg]:
_Theorem_: [P] implies [~~P], for any proposition [P]. *)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(* Do not modify the following line: *)
Definition manual_grade_for_double_neg_inf : option (nat*string) := None.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard, especially useful (contrapositive) *)
Theorem contrapositive : forall (P Q : Prop),
(P -> Q) -> (~Q -> ~P).
Proof.
intros P Q H Q' P'.
apply H in P'. apply Q' in P'. apply P'.
Qed.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, standard (not_both_true_and_false) *)
Theorem not_both_true_and_false : forall P : Prop,
~ (P /\ ~P).
Proof.
intros P.
unfold not.
intros [L R].
apply R in L. destruct L.
Qed.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, advanced (informal_not_PNP)
Write an informal proof (in English) of the proposition [forall P
: Prop, ~(P /\ ~P)]. *)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(* Do not modify the following line: *)
Definition manual_grade_for_informal_not_PNP : option (nat*string) := None.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard (de_morgan_not_or)
_De Morgan's Laws_, named for Augustus De Morgan, describe how
negation interacts with conjunction and disjunction. The
following law says that "the negation of a disjunction is the
conjunction of the negations." There is a corresponding law
[de_morgan_not_and_not] that we will return to at the end of this
chapter. *)
Theorem de_morgan_not_or : forall (P Q : Prop),
~ (P \/ Q) -> ~P /\ ~Q.
Proof.
intros P Q H.
unfold not in H.
split.
- intros H'. apply or_intro_l with (B := Q) in H'. apply H in H'. destruct H'.
- intros H'. apply or_intro_l with (B := P) in H'. apply or_commut in H'. apply H in H'. destruct H'.
Qed.
(** [] *)
(** Since inequality involves a negation, it also requires a little
practice to be able to work with it fluently. Here is one useful
trick.
If you are trying to prove a goal that is nonsensical (e.g., the
goal state is [false = true]), apply [ex_falso_quodlibet] to
change the goal to [False].
This makes it easier to use assumptions of the form [~P] that may
be available in the context -- in particular, assumptions of the
form [x<>y]. *)
Theorem not_true_is_false : forall b : bool,
b <> true -> b = false.
Proof.
intros b H.
destruct b eqn:HE.
- (* b = true *)
unfold not in H.
apply ex_falso_quodlibet.
apply H. reflexivity.
- (* b = false *)
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** Since reasoning with [ex_falso_quodlibet] is quite common, Coq
provides a built-in tactic, [exfalso], for applying it. *)
Theorem not_true_is_false' : forall b : bool,
b <> true -> b = false.
Proof.
intros [] H. (* note implicit [destruct b] here *)
- (* b = true *)
unfold not in H.
exfalso. (* <=== *)
apply H. reflexivity.
- (* b = false *) reflexivity.
Qed.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Truth *)
(** Besides [False], Coq's standard library also defines [True], a
proposition that is trivially true. To prove it, we use the
constant [I : True], which is also defined in the standard
library: *)
Lemma True_is_true : True.
Proof. apply I. Qed.
(** Unlike [False], which is used extensively, [True] is used
relatively rarely, since it is trivial (and therefore
uninteresting) to prove as a goal, and conversely it provides no
interesting information when used as a hypothesis. *)
(** However, [True] can be quite useful when defining complex [Prop]s using
conditionals or as a parameter to higher-order [Prop]s. We'll come back
to this later.
For now, let's take a look at how we can use [True] and [False] to
achieve an effect similar to that of the [discriminate] tactic, without
literally using [discriminate]. *)
(** Pattern-matching lets us do different things for different
constructors. If the result of applying two different
constructors were hypothetically equal, then we could use [match]
to convert an unprovable statement (like [False]) to one that is
provable (like [True]). *)
Definition disc_fn (n: nat) : Prop :=
match n with
| O => True
| S _ => False
end.
Theorem disc_example : forall n, ~ (O = S n).
Proof.
intros n H1.
assert (H2 : disc_fn O). { simpl. apply I. }
rewrite H1 in H2. simpl in H2. apply H2.
Qed.
(** To generalize this to other constructors, we simply have to provide an
appropriate variant of [disc_fn]. To generalize it to other
conclusions, we can use [exfalso] to replace them with [False].
The built-in [discriminate] tactic takes care of all this for us! *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Logical Equivalence *)
(** The handy "if and only if" connective, which asserts that two
propositions have the same truth value, is simply the conjunction
of two implications. *)
Module IffPlayground.
Definition iff (P Q : Prop) := (P -> Q) /\ (Q -> P).
Notation "P <-> Q" := (iff P Q)
(at level 95, no associativity)
: type_scope.
End IffPlayground.
Theorem iff_sym : forall P Q : Prop,
(P <-> Q) -> (Q <-> P).
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros P Q [HAB HBA].
split.
- (* -> *) apply HBA.
- (* <- *) apply HAB. Qed.
Lemma not_true_iff_false : forall b,
b <> true <-> b = false.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros b. split.
- (* -> *) apply not_true_is_false.
- (* <- *)
intros H. rewrite H. discriminate.
Qed.
(** The [apply] tactic can also be used with [<->]. We can use
[apply] on an [<->] in either direction, without explicitly thinking
about the fact that it is really an [and] underneath. *)
Lemma apply_iff_example1:
forall P Q R : Prop, (P <-> Q) -> (Q -> R) -> (P -> R).
intros P Q R Hiff H HP. apply H. apply Hiff. apply HP.
Qed.
Lemma apply_iff_example2:
forall P Q R : Prop, (P <-> Q) -> (P -> R) -> (Q -> R).
intros P Q R Hiff H HQ. apply H. apply Hiff. apply HQ.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, standard, optional (iff_properties)
Using the above proof that [<->] is symmetric ([iff_sym]) as
a guide, prove that it is also reflexive and transitive. *)
Theorem iff_refl : forall P : Prop,
P <-> P.
Proof.
intros P.
split.
- intros P'. apply P'.
- intros P'. apply P'.
Qed.
Theorem iff_trans : forall P Q R : Prop,
(P <-> Q) -> (Q <-> R) -> (P <-> R).
Proof.
intros P Q R.
split.
- intros HP. apply H0. apply H. apply HP.
- intros HR. apply H. apply H0. apply HR.
Qed.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard (or_distributes_over_and) *)
Lemma and_intro : forall A B : Prop, A -> B -> A /\ B.
Proof.
intros A B HA HB. split.
- apply HA.
- apply HB.
Qed.
Theorem or_distributes_over_and : forall P Q R : Prop,
P \/ (Q /\ R) <-> (P \/ Q) /\ (P \/ R).
Proof.
intros P Q R.
split.
(** forward implication proof *)
- intros [HP | [HQ HR] ]. (* this syntax allows for an implict destruct, by introducing propositions into the context, indirectly presuming them to be true. *)
+ split.
apply or_intro_l with (B := Q) in HP. apply HP.
apply or_intro_l with (B := R) in HP. apply HP.
+ split.
apply or_intro_l with (B := P) in HQ. apply or_commut in HQ. apply HQ.
apply or_intro_l with (B := P) in HR. apply or_commut in HR. apply HR.
- intros [ [HP1 | HPQ] [HP2 | HPR] ].
+ left. apply HP1.
+ left. apply HP1.
+ left. apply HP2.
+ right. apply and_intro. apply HPQ. apply HPR.
Qed.
(** [] *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Setoids and Logical Equivalence *)
(** Some of Coq's tactics treat [iff] statements specially, avoiding some
low-level proof-state manipulation. In particular, [rewrite] and
[reflexivity] can be used with [iff] statements, not just equalities.
To enable this behavior, we have to import the Coq library that
supports it: *)
From Coq Require Import Setoids.Setoid.
(** A "setoid" is a set equipped with an equivalence relation -- that
is, a relation that is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive. When two
elements of a set are equivalent according to the relation, [rewrite]
can be used to replace one by the other.
We've seen this already with the equality relation [=] in Coq: when
[x = y], we can use [rewrite] to replace [x] with [y] or vice-versa.
Similarly, the logical equivalence relation [<->] is reflexive,
symmetric, and transitive, so we can use it to replace one part of a
proposition with another: if [P <-> Q], then we can use [rewrite] to
replace [P] with [Q], or vice-versa. *)
(** Here is a simple example demonstrating how these tactics work with
[iff].
First, let's prove a couple of basic iff equivalences. *)
Lemma mul_eq_0 : forall n m, n * m = 0 <-> n = 0 \/ m = 0.
Proof.
split.
- apply mult_is_O.
- apply factor_is_O.
Qed.
Theorem or_assoc :
forall P Q R : Prop, P \/ (Q \/ R) <-> (P \/ Q) \/ R.
Proof.
intros P Q R. split.
- intros [H | [H | H]].
+ left. left. apply H.
+ left. right. apply H.
+ right. apply H.
- intros [[H | H] | H].
+ left. apply H.
+ right. left. apply H.
+ right. right. apply H.
Qed.
(* Recall that the left and right tactics apply for disjunctions, since both sides are always True. *)
(** We can now use these facts with [rewrite] and [reflexivity] to
give smooth proofs of statements involving equivalences. For example,
here is a ternary version of the previous [mult_0] result: *)
Lemma mul_eq_0_ternary :
forall n m p, n * m * p = 0 <-> n = 0 \/ m = 0 \/ p = 0.
Proof.
intros n m p.
rewrite mul_eq_0. rewrite mul_eq_0. rewrite or_assoc.
reflexivity.
Qed.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Existential Quantification *)
(** Another basic logical connective is _existential quantification_.
To say that there is some [x] of type [T] such that some property [P]
holds of [x], we write [exists x : T, P]. As with [forall], the type
annotation [: T] can be omitted if Coq is able to infer from the
context what the type of [x] should be. *)
(** To prove a statement of the form [exists x, P], we must show that [P]
holds for some specific choice for [x], known as the _witness_ of the
existential. This is done in two steps: First, we explicitly tell Coq
which witness [t] we have in mind by invoking the tactic [exists t].
Then we prove that [P] holds after all occurrences of [x] are replaced
by [t]. *)
Definition Even x := exists n : nat, x = double n.
Lemma four_is_Even : Even 4.
Proof.
unfold Even. exists 2. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** Conversely, if we have an existential hypothesis [exists x, P] in
the context, we can destruct it to obtain a witness [x] and a
hypothesis stating that [P] holds of [x]. *)
Theorem exists_example_2 : forall n,
(exists m, n = 4 + m) ->
(exists o, n = 2 + o).
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros n [m Hm]. (* note the implicit [destruct] here *)
exists (2 + m).
apply Hm. Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, standard, especially useful (dist_not_exists)
Prove that "[P] holds for all [x]" implies "there is no [x] for
which [P] does not hold." (Hint: [destruct H as [x E]] works on
existential assumptions!) *)
Theorem dist_not_exists : forall (X:Type) (P : X -> Prop),
(forall x, P x) -> ~ (exists x, ~ P x).
Proof.
unfold not.
intros X P HP HP'.
destruct HP' as [x H].
- apply H. apply HP.
Qed.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard (dist_exists_or)
Prove that existential quantification distributes over
disjunction. *)
Theorem dist_exists_or : forall (X:Type) (P Q : X -> Prop),
(exists x, P x \/ Q x) <-> (exists x, P x) \/ (exists x, Q x).
Proof.
intros X P Q.
split.
- intros [x [HP | HQ] ].
left. exists x. apply HP.
right. exists x. apply HQ.
- intros [ [x HP] | [x' HQ] ].
exists x. left. apply HP.
exists x'. right. apply HQ.
Qed.
(** [] *)
Lemma minus_identity : forall (n : nat), n = n - 0.
Proof.
induction n.
- simpl. reflexivity.
- simpl. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard, optional (leb_plus_exists) *)
Theorem leb_plus_exists : forall n m, n <=? m = true -> exists x, m = n+x.
Proof.
intros n m H.
exists (m - n).
induction n as [|n' IHn'].
- simpl. apply minus_identity.
Admitted.
Theorem plus_exists_leb : forall n m, (exists x, m = n+x) -> n <=? m = true.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Programming with Propositions *)
(** The logical connectives that we have seen provide a rich
vocabulary for defining complex propositions from simpler ones.
To illustrate, let's look at how to express the claim that an
element [x] occurs in a list [l]. Notice that this property has a
simple recursive structure:
- If [l] is the empty list, then [x] cannot occur in it, so the
property "[x] appears in [l]" is simply false.
- Otherwise, [l] has the form [x' :: l']. In this case, [x]
occurs in [l] if it is equal to [x'] or if it occurs in
[l']. *)
(** We can translate this directly into a straightforward recursive
function taking an element and a list and returning a proposition (!): *)
Fixpoint In {A : Type} (x : A) (l : list A) : Prop :=
match l with
| [] => False
| x' :: l' => x' = x \/ In x l'
end.
(** When [In] is applied to a concrete list, it expands into a
concrete sequence of nested disjunctions. *)
Example In_example_1 : In 4 [1; 2; 3; 4; 5].
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
simpl. right. right. right. left. reflexivity.
Qed.
Example In_example_2 :
forall n, In n [2; 4] ->
exists n', n = 2 * n'.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
simpl.
intros n [H | [H | []]].
- exists 1. rewrite <- H. reflexivity.
- exists 2. rewrite <- H. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** (Notice the use of the empty pattern to discharge the last case
_en passant_.) *)
(** We can also reason about more generic statements involving [In]. *)
Theorem In_map :
forall (A B : Type) (f : A -> B) (l : list A) (x : A),
In x l ->
In (f x) (map f l).
Proof.
intros A B f l x.
induction l as [|x' l' IHl'].
- (* l = nil, contradiction *)
simpl. intros [].
- (* l = x' :: l' *)
simpl. intros [H | H].
+ rewrite H. left. reflexivity.
+ right. apply IHl'. apply H.
Qed.
(** (Note here how [In] starts out applied to a variable and only
gets expanded when we do case analysis on this variable.) *)
(** This way of defining propositions recursively is very convenient in
some cases, less so in others. In particular, it is subject to Coq's
usual restrictions regarding the definition of recursive functions,
e.g., the requirement that they be "obviously terminating."
In the next chapter, we will see how to define propositions
_inductively_ -- a different technique with its own strengths and
limitations. *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard (In_map_iff) *)
Theorem In_map_iff :
forall (A B : Type) (f : A -> B) (l : list A) (y : B),
In y (map f l) <->
exists x, f x = y /\ In x l.
Proof.
intros A B f l y. split.
induction l as [|a' l' IHl'].
- simpl. intros H. exfalso. contradiction.
- simpl. intros [HA | HB ].
(** HA *)
exists a'.
split.
apply HA.
simpl. left. reflexivity.
(** HB *)
apply IHl' in HB. destruct HB as [x [H1 H2] ].
exists x. split.
+ apply H1.
+ right. apply H2.
- intros [x [HA HB] ].
rewrite <- HA. apply In_map. apply HB.
Qed.
(** [] *)
Search list.
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard (In_app_iff) *)
Theorem In_app_iff : forall A l l' (a:A),
In a (l++l') <-> In a l \/ In a l'.
Proof.
intros A l. induction l as [|a' l' IH].
split.
(** l = nil *)
(** forward *)